SOME MISCONCEPTIONS OF MULTILINEAR EVOLUTION1 William C. Smith It is the object of this paper to consider certain conceptual difficulties in Julian Steward's theory of multillnear evolution. The particular concepts with which we shall be concerned may be grouped into four pairs, reflecting the order of discussion to be followed: these concepts are (1) "evolution" and "evolutionism"; (2) "culture change" and "cultural evolution"; (3) "unilinear" and "multilinear" evolution; and (4) "causality" and "law." In the published works of Julian Steward (as elsewhere) the term "evolu- tion" is often used to denote two concepts which, while not unrelated, should be distinguished if mi sunderstanding is to be avoided. These two concepts may be referred to by the terms "evolution" and "evolutionism-" '"Evolution" here denotes "developuiental process": it is this meaning which Steward wishes to convey when he says that certain nineteenth century thinkers held that every- where "cultural evolution must be governed by the same principles and follow the same line, and [that] all mankind would progress toward a civilization like that of Europe" (1956:69). "Evolutionism" on the other hand refers to a point of view, a body of theory, a methodology: thus Steward refers to "the evolu- tionism of White and Childe"f (1953.317). But evolution (as process) and evolu- tionism (as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says, for example, that "The facts now accumulated indicate that human culture evolved along a number of different lines; we must think of cultural evolution not as unilinear but as mrultilinear. * O" (1956:73)--clearly speaking of evol- ution as a process; but elsewhere he states that "Multilinear evolution is essentially a methodology. ott (1956:318). In any evernt, it is with evolution as methodology that Steward is primarily concerned. He contrasts "evolution" and "culture change,," for example, not as distinct processes to, be' studied, but as basically different theoretical orien- tations or methodologies. Thus he seems to equate "culture change" with "cul- tural relativism and historical particularism" as a methodological view differ- ent from that of "cultural evolution," which he defines as "a quest for cultural regularities or laws. * o" (9153315). Now it might be argued that even If Steward does often use the term "evolution" to refer to methodology rather than to process, he may nevertheless intend to imply something of proc- ess. This may indeed be the case; but inasmuch as "cultural evolution" refers to a process to be studied, it should be possible to distinguish this process from other cultural processes--such as, for example, cultural change. How- ever, we have seen that these processes are defined in Steward's writing only by implication; and the implication is that "cultural evolution" is a process which lends itself to study by the method of empirical scientific inquiry; while "culture change" is a process more amenable to treatment by what Steward calls the methods of "cultural relativism and historical particularism" (5953: 3l5). Now the notion that some processes can be studied scientifically while others (namlely the "historical") cannot, is not a new one. In speaking of some of the earlier manifestations of this idea, Kenneth Bock has said: "Adher- ence to this view can confuse the issue. . . The belief that some things come about by a series of happenings singular to each of them and other things come about by comparable or like processes, or even the belief that among common processes there will be some unique aspects, are conclusions that can be reached only through comparison; they are not warranted or serviceable as assumptions from which inquiry takes its departure' (l956:113). The processes of culture change and cultural evolution can be distinguished in these terms only as a result of inquiry--thus the distinction between them cannot reasonably be used in defining the methods by which they are to be studied. In short, if we at- tempt to regard Steward's term "evolution" as referring to a process, we find that the process remains quite ambiguously defined. We shall therefore abandon this contention, and accept the view that by "evolution" Steward does in fact mean (as he has declared) "methodology." Steward has distinguished three forms of the methodology which he calls "evolution7': these are unilinear evolution, universal evolution, and multi- linear evolution. Unilinear evolution deals with particular cultures, placing them in stages of a universal sequence; but, according to Steward, ethnographic data have demonstrated that there are no stages through which all cultures have passed or must pass. Universal evolution deals with "culture" rather than with "cultures"; but to Steward its assertions are so general and trivial as to be of little interest. Multilinear evolution deals with particular cultures, and asserts that particular cases of parallel development follow from the operation of particular causes; it seeks empirically verifiable generalizations, but not universal ones. Thus multilinear evolution retains the generalizing, scientific character which Steward sees in. all evolutionary schemes, but attempts to tie these closer to empirical reality (1953:315-318). What, then, is characteristic and distinctive in the methodology of multi- linear evolution as contrasted with that of unilinear and universal evolution? Multilinear evolution is a more modest approach, we are told: flit is distinc- tive in searching for parallels of limited occurrence instead of universals" (1953:315). It seems clear that to Steward this is a point of methodological virtue, but one may question both its necessity and its desirability. -Surely, generalizations (or "parallels") pertaining to all societies are as valuable as those pertaining only to some societies; and the range of the generalizations we seek from a given body of data should be regarded as a matter to be decided by empirical inquiry--not as an a priori limitation upon inquiry. While the universal assertions of the ninetee century evolutionists have proven empiri- cally false, this does not imply that making such assertions or asking such questions is methodologically undesirable. A methodology which rules out such questions does so at its own risk; and, one may suggest, limits itself unneces- sarily. But it is by just this limitation that Steward distinguishes the methodology of multilinear evolution from other evolutionary schemes. To the extent that it is nothing more than an a priori limitation upon inquiry, it may with reason be distrusted as a methodology. But is it really nothing more? A brief glance at the methodology of multilinear evolution in action may throw some light upon the matter. Steward has defined "multilinear evolution"1 as -"a methodology based on the assumption that si gnificant regular ities in cultural change occur, and . . concerned with the determination of cultural laws" (1953:318). In the essay, "Cultural Causality and Law," he sets forth the following program: "'(1) There must be a typology of cultures, patterns, and institutions. . . (2) Causal interrelationship of types must be established in sequential,or syn- chronic terms, or both. . E (3) The formulation of the independent recurrence of synchronic and/or sequential interrelationships of cultural phenomena is a scientific statement of cause and effect, regularities, or laws" (1955:180- 181). Due to lack of space the matter of typology cannot be discussed here; but even assuming the availability of an adequate typology, there are certain difficulties in Steward's concept of causality which invite examination. There are, in Steward's tems, two aspects to the formulation of cultural regularities or laws: (a) the establishment of causal interrelationships of types, and (b) the recognition of independent (cross-cultural) recurrence of such relationships. Now it would seem that (b) would necessarily presuppose (a)--that is, that causal relationships must be established initially before they can be recognized cross-culturally. But it is by no means clear how causal relationships are to be established in the first place. We find, for example, that in Mesopotamia, settled village agriculture preceded urban settlement; but can we therefore simply conclude that the former caused the latter? Not without committing the fallacy of post hoc, ergo propter hoc And if we cannot establish causal relationships initially, how can we hope to recognize their cross-cultural recurrence? The dilemma is not really as serious as this, however. Steward simply does not start with the determination of causal relationships; he starts, rather, with the observation of parallel, recurrent cultural sequences (1953: 323; 1955:185-198). He begins, for example, by recognizing the recurrence of several "eras" (each characterized by a particular set of economic and social institutions) in the development of early civilization in five major areas of the world. The mere recognition of such recurrence of sequential development, he suggests (1955:199), could be considered as a formulation of cross-cultural regularity or law. But such a formulation would be superficial, Steward feels, in failing to provide "a satisfactory and generally valid functional explana- tion of cause-and-effect relationshipsO v *t. He then proceeds to suggest an explanation for these recurring sequences. Clearly then, the method employed is to start with parallel sequential developments, then attempt to construct a suitable explanation which accounts for all the data. But a curious thing has happened here: in the program which Steward has previously outlined, no mention was made of the need for both formulation of cross-cultural regulari- ties and explanation of such regularities; and while it would readily be granted that both are desirable, it is legitimate to wonder which is to be taken as a statement of cultural law--regularity, or explanation of regularity? While the point at issue here is a subtle and important one (cf. Popper 1957: 124), it may be assumed that regularities must be established before they can be explained; and that in Steward's usage "regularity" and "law" are inter- changeable (Steward 1953:315; 1955:181-185). Further difficulties in Steward's notion of causality appear in his dis- cussion of the patrilineal And. Having noted that certain characteristics were present among a numzber widely separated primitive societies, he then succeeded in relating these dparacterlstics functionally; from this he concludes that they are causally related, and that the patrilineal band is the result of a (sequentially unspecified) "line of evolution" (Steward 1955:122-142; 1956; 74-75). Granting that certain patterns of subsistence technology, settlement pattern, and social organization can be seen as functionally related--that is, as contributing to the persistence of the total socio-cultural system of which they form a part--one may still ask how it is possible to jump from this to a statement of causal relationship. Steward asserts that causal relationships can be synchronic and functional, as well as diachronic and sequential (1955: 180-181). It seems ambiguous to say that one event can "cause" another event with which it occurs simultaneously; but to press the matter further would involve us in a morass of epistemological analysis. The difficulty of deriving causal relations from functional, synchronic ones is clearly indicated by H. M. Blalock, Jr. in a recent article in the American Anthropologist (1960:624-631). Cohen and Nagel (193h:245-249), in a standard handbook on scientific method, dismiss the whole issue by speaking not of causal relations but of invariant relations, uniformities, regularities--of order, in short. To the extent that this questionable notion of causality is an essential feature of the methodology of multilinear evolution, one would be justified in questioning the validity of the whole method. But it might be argued that causality is not essential to any of Stewardts substantive discussions--that these discussions have as their aim the formulation of significant cross-cul*; tural regularities; and that in this they are generally successful. With the latter point I would agree. Let us assume, then, that the cultural laws which are Steward's aim are to be formulated upon the basis of the cross-cultural recurrence of regular, invariant relationships between various cultural elements or patterns., We can say that the "methodology" which Steward advocates is sim- ply that of searching for such regularities, of formulating such laws. It is this methodology which Steward calls "multilinear evolution"; it is "multiline- ar" because there are many such regularities which pertain only to some (not all) societies; and it is "evolutione because Steward has defined "evolution" as a quest for cultural regularities. But, after all, one could say that all scientific endeavor has as its aim the discovery, formulation, and expnation of regularities--that is, of recurrent invariant relationships (cf. Cohen and Nagel 1934:245-249, 391-402). Perhaps Steward's methodology is simply the method of empirical scientific inquiry, applied to culture. If this is not the case, then one might wonder why Steward has not bothered to point out the dif- ference. But if "cultvral evolutione as method is indistinguishable from "science" as method, it seems reasonable to suggest that the latter term, more comprehensive in scope as well as more widely accepted, would be preferable. What I have tried to suggest may be summarized as follows: first, Steward does not clearly distinguish between "evolution" as a process to be studied and "evolutionism" as a body of theory or a point of view. If we take his notion of "evolution" to refer to a process, we find that it is distinguished from the process of "culture change" in a rather misleading way--that is, by the assump- tion that the process of "evolution" can be studied scientifically, while the process of "culture change" can be treated only historically and particularis- tically. This may be true; but if so it is a conclusion which should follow from empirical inquiry, and can hardly serve as an assumption upon which inquiry is to be based. If on the other hand we take Steward's notion of "evolution" to refer not to process but rather to mcethodology ("the methodology of multilinear evolution") we find, first, that it is distinguished from other "evolutionary" methodologies (e.g., that of "unilinear evolution") only by the somewhat arbitrary a priori decision not to seek for generalizations applying to all societies. Apart from this matter of arbitrary limitation, Steward's method- ology is unclear on the difficult matter of causality: first, it is not clear how statements of causal relationship are to be established or tested; second, it is not clear how statements of causality are related to statements which formulate crosscultural regularities and those which explain such regularities. Finally, if we eliminate from the methodology of multilinear evolution both its difficult notion of causality and its arbitrary limitations upon inquiry., we are left with what amounts to the search for invariant relations, unifomities, regularities, or order in cultural phenomena. If the search for order in empirical phenomena is, as some philosophers of science have suggested, the essential characteristic of scientific inquiry, it is difficult to see how the tmethodology of multilinear evolution" differs from "scientific inquiry into cultural phenomena." It is just such inquiry, I think, that Steward means to encourage; it is undoubtedly well represented in his own substantive work. In constructing a methodology with which to advance such inquiry, however, Steward makes certain assumptions which I feel are neither necessary nor fully Justified. It has been the purpose of this paper to call attention to these questionable points in Steward's methodology, in the hope that such continued discussion of method- ology will further the work with which Steward has long been concerned. ENDNOTE (1) The writer is indebted to Professor John H. Rowe for critical reading of this manuscript; but for errors of interpretation the writer alone is responsible. BIBLIOGRAPHY Blalock, H. M., Jr. 1960 Correlational analysis and causal inference. American Anthropolo- gist 62:624-631. Bock, Kenneth 1956 The acceptance of histories: toward a perspective for social science. Cohen, Morris R., and Ernest Nagel 1934 An introduction to logic and scientific method. Popper, Karl R. 1957 The poverty of historicism. 1959 The logic of scientific discovery. Steward, Julian H. 1953 Evolution and process. In Anthropology Today, A. L. Kroeber (ed.), pp. 313-326. 1955 Theor-y of culture change: the methodology of multilinear evolu- tion. 1956 Cultural evolution. Scientific American 194:69-800 54~